web metrics
SOME REMARKS ON THE
COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT
1

John Byl, Ph.D.

Rational proofs for the existence of God date back to at least the time of Plato. Of these various theological existence proofs the cosmological argument, which postulates that there must be a prior Cause to explain the existence of the universe, is probably the most popular. Over the years many different versions of it have been presented. Geisler & Corduan affirm that only the cosmological argument offers hope for a theistic proof;2 much of their philosophy of religion rests upon its presumed validity.

Our focus will be on the Kalam Cosmological Argument, which aims to demonstrate that the universe was created a finite time ago by a personal creator. The argument is grounded upon the supposed impossibility of an actual infinity of past events.

Many of the arguments against an actual infinity can be traced back to Aristotle, although the Christian philosopher John Philoponus seems to have been the first to apply them (in 529 A.D.) to a demonstration of the finite age of the universe.3 Philoponus' proofs for creation were taken up and further developed in the 9th and 10th centuries by a number of Islamic philosophers of the Kalam school, becoming thus known as the Kalam cosmological argument.4

In recent times it has been defended by several Christian apologists, including William Craig5 and J. P. Moreland.6 It boils down to the following reasoning:

(1) the universe had a beginning.
(2) the beginning of the universe was caused.
(3) that cause was personal.

In short, the finite past of the universe implies its ex nihilo creation by a personal creator.

Our prime concern here is with step (1), particularly with the claim that an actual infinite cannot exist.

The supposed impossibility of the actual infinite is central not only to the Kalam cosmological argument, but also to the cosmological argument as defended by Geisler & Corduan, which takes on a rather different form. We shall first address the question as to whether arguments against the actual infinite are in fact valid. Then, supposing they are, we shall examine various theological implications.

Is an Actual Infinite Impossible?

The most common objection to a beginningless past is that this requires the crossing of an infinite number of years. This is held to be impossible since, if we start counting 1,2,3…, we could never reach infinity. The series of numbers counted would increase forever, but it would always be finite. Hence today would never arrive.7
Such argumentation assumes that there exists a past year that is separated from the present by an infinity of years. But this is not the case for a beginningless past. If we number the past years, counting back from the present, as 0,-1,-2,…, then the set of past years corresponds to the set of negative integers. The set as a whole is certainly infinite, but no two negative integers are ever infinitely far apart. Infinity is a property of the set as a whole, not of any particular member of the set.

Moreover, if it were true that the universe must have had a beginning a finite number of years ago, which year would it be? For any finite year one might care to name one could always add one to it. As there is no bound to the negative numbers, so likewise there need be no bound to the number of past years.
William Craig has constructed a variety of further arguments against an actual infinity. These can be grouped into three categories:

(1) it is impossible to add to an actually infinite collection.
(2) the fact that infinite collections are all of equal size leads to contradictions.
(3) a collection formed by adding one member after another cannot be actually infinite.

These arguments have been examined in detail by Quentin Smith,8 who finds them to be fallacious and who concludes that there is no philosophical objection to an infinite past (although Smith does believe that there are valid scientific objections to it). It is not my intent to repeat Smith's analysis, which I believe to be correct, but only to note a few major concerns.

I believe that the prime confusion arises from the fact that Craig often assesses infinite sets by criteria that properly apply only to finite sets. Infinite sets certainly have strange properties. For example, if w represents infinity, then 1 + w = w; 2 x w = w; and even w x w = w. Since we are used to dealing concretely only with finite sets, such properties of infinite sets do seem almost unbelievable. Nevertheless, as demonstrated by Georg Cantor (1845-1918) and confirmed by modern mathematicians, trans-finite mathematics is logically consistent. Although a number of paradoxes can arise in the usage of infinite sets, these are generally a result of self-reference problems.

Craig notes that he is arguing only against an actual infinity in the real world, and in no way wishes to undermine the concept of actual infinity as found in Cantorian transfinite mathematics. But there, according to Craig, actual infinity is only an idea:

What I shall argue is that while the actual infinite may be a fruitful and consistent concept in the mathematical realm, it cannot be translated from the mathematical world into the real world, for this would involve counter-intuitive absurdities.9

He gives a number of illustrations, one being a library consisting of an infinite number of books. Such a library has some strange properties. For example, if we eliminate half of the books (i.e., the odd-numbered ones) then we still have as many books as we stayed with. Yet if we now loan out the remaining books (i.e., the even-numbered ones) then we have nothing left, even though we have removed exactly the same number as before. Furthermore, Craig argues, if we add a book to an infinite library then we can see that the collection is increased by one; we don't have the same number of books as before, as should be the case for an infinite set. He concludes that such examples serve to illustrate that an actual infinite cannot exist in the real world.

Does this argument really demonstrate the impossibility of an actual infinity in the real world? I think not. The above operations on books could also be done on, say, the positive integers. Remove the odd ones and you still have an infinity left; remove now also the even ones and nothing remains. Or take the even integers, which form an infinite set, and you can still add any odd number to it, leaving us still with an infinite set. If these operations are permissible for numbers, why not also for books? Since one could set up a one-to-one correspondence between integers and books in a library (or events in time), it follows that likewise an actual infinity of books (or events) need not involve any logical difficulties, however counter-intuitive such an actual infinite library might be.

The essential distinction between books and numbers, according to Craig, is that the former are concrete things while the latter are mere ideas. We can see and feel books and hence, presumably, counter- intuitive notions must be rejected. Yet one might question whether it is meaningful for us to even contemplate the occurrence of an actual infinity in the real world of our experiences. After all, within the limitations of our finite experiences, memories, and thoughts we can never distinguish between the infinite and merely the very large. Even if we could eliminate half of the books in an infinite library, the remainder will sell be beyond our ability to count and thus, in any practical sense, will be the same as what we started with. Since all our human experiences are finite, the real actual infinite is necessarily counter-intuitive. But that by itself does not render it impossible.

God and the Future

Suppose, for the sake of the argument, that the proofs against the actual infinite were valid. Such a ban on the actual infinite would have some awkward theological consequences. Consider, first of all, the question of future events. The Bible, in its description of the life-hereafter, pictures it as a temporal existence, with flowing water and ripening fruit, where the saints shall reign for ever and ever (Rev.22:1-5): a seemingly endless future time. Is this view of the future not ruled out by the arguments against an actual infinity of past events, which imply that the future must likewise be finite?
Craig argues that this need not be the case. The future differs from the past in that it is not an actual completed infinity; it is only potentially infinite, in the sense of being inexhaustible. A potential infinity is, according to Craig, permissible:

a potential infinite is a collection that is increasing without limit but is at all times finite…it is not truly infinite - it is simply indefinite.10

Past events are real since they have actually occurred; future events, asserts Craig, do not actually exist because they have not (yet) occurred.
At fast sight such a past/future distinction seems valid enough. However, when applied to the omniscient God of orthodox theology (and it must be kept in mind that this is just a step in an alleged proof for the existence of such a God), it becomes problematic. After all, such a God knows the future as definitely as He knows the past. If the future is indeed endless, then to an omniscient God it exists as a definite actual infinity, rather than as an indefinite potential infinity. It would seem that to God an endless future would have the same status as a beginningless past. Both entail the notion that God has an infinite stock of memories or thoughts (cf. Ps. 139:17).

Thus the considerations leading to a finite past must similarly apply to the future. If Crag's argument against an actual infinity is valid it implies that God's knowledge encompasses only a finite number of future events. This leads to the conclusion that either the future is finite, and there is a last event, or God's knowledge of the future is incomplete.

God and the Past

There are further difficulties. Crag's arguments against the real existence of actual infinity are sufficiency general that they seem to apply not only to the physical universe, but also to God Himself. This must have significant implications for God, who is generally considered in orthodox theology to be infinite.

For example, Crag's ban on the actual infinite implies that also God's past must then be finite. Indeed, Craig himself comes to this conclusion:

… prior to creation God would have to be changeless. Otherwise you would get an infinite series of past events in God's life, and we have seen that such an infinite series is impossible. So God would be changeless and hence, timeless prior to creation.11

It seems that Craig views God as being essentially “frozen” for an infinite time before the fast event. This seems to place rather stringent conditions on the nature of God, ruling out any succession of acts or thoughts prior to creation.

It is interesting that Craig applies the prohibition of an actual infinity only to events, and not to the passage of time itself. He does allow for a past infinity of time. Is it permissible to allow an infinity of past time while ruling out an infinity of past events (i.e., an eternal “frozen” universe)? Even then there would still be the everlasting passage from one time unit to the next, else how is infinite time to be distinguished from an isolated unit of time?

It could be argued that, since there are no physical events to measure this time, we are not confronted with an actual infinity. But does this limitation apply to God? If God is omniscient then He must know also of the passage of time. To God, it would seem, even the passage of a unit of time is something “which happens” and thus should count as an event. If God has existed through a past infinity of time then an actual infinity of units of time has elapsed. It follows that God's knowledge of a past that consists of finite events embedded within infinite time must include knowledge of an actual infinity of past units of time.

Furthermore, the admission that time itself has a finite past endangers Craig's argument for a personal creator. Craig's argument for the first cause being a personal agent rests upon the assumption that there was an infinite timespan before creation. Since all moments in such an infinite time are alike, he argues, it requires a personal being to freely choose to create at any time wholly apart from any distinguishing conditions of one moment from another.12 Elsewhere Craig affirms that the only way to have an eternal cause but an effect that begins at a point in time is if the cause is a personal agent who freely decides to create an effect in time. For example, a man sitting from eternity may will to get up.13
The conclusion to which we are led, assuming that the actual infinite can't exist, is that the universe, time, and God all started to exist a finite time past.

To summarize, a ban on the actual infinite seems to place undue restrictions not only on the past, but also on the future, on God, and on time itself. Although there may be aspects of infinity that appear incomprehensible to us, it seems to me that, in the absence of water-tight logical disproofs of actual infinity, the better course is to attribute this per ceived deficiency to human finiteness rather than to confer undue constraints upon God and His attributes.

For the cosmological argument to work without placing unwarranted limitations on God it is necessary to make a proper distinction between Creator and creation. The demonstration of the finite past of the physical universe is therefore perhaps better based on physical, rather than logical, grounds. Two main lines of evidence are often cited as scientific proof for the beginning of the universe: the big bang singularity and the second law of thermodynamics.

It is beyond the scope of this paper to examine in detail the alleged scientific evidence for a beginning of the universe. Since such scientific conclusions must go beyond current observations, they are necessarily speculative: it is possible to devise many plausible cosmological models that avoid a beginning in time. Even if this were not the case, if only a finite-past Big Bang cosmology were scientifically viable, this would still involve unverifiable assumptions such as, for example, that of the universal applicability (always and everywhere) of the physical laws observed here and now. How, for example, can we be sure that no miracles have occurred? Certainly, as a step in a proof for the existence of the Biblical God, any scientific proof of a beginning of the universe is unsatisfactory since an omniscient and omnipotent God could well have interacted with the universe, perhaps in miraculous ways, so as to avoid the limitations of thermodynamics and space-time singularities. The best one could do is argue that any theistic implications of naturalistic big bang cosmology imply, not the truth of big bang cosmology but rather the deficiency of naturalism.

In short, the case for the existence of God based upon purely logical or scientific proofs for a finite past of the universe are ultimately self- defeating: a ban on the actual infinite places undue constraints on God; scientific proof for a beginning assumes the absence of supernatural events.


NOTES AND REFERENCES

1 An earlier version of this material is being published as part of a longer paper “On Craig's Defence of the Kalam Cosmological Argument" in Proceedings of the Pascal Centre Internation Conference on Science and Belief, (held August 11-15, 1992, Redeemer College.

2 Norman Geisler & Winfred Corduan, Philosophy of Religion (Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1988, 2nd ed.), p.l50.

3 See Richard Sorabji, Eme, Creation and the Continuum (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983), p.l98.

4 See Herbert A. Davidson, Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islanuc and Jewish Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 117-153.

5 William L. Craig, The Kalam Cosmological Argument (London: Macmillan, 1979).

6 J. P. Moreland, The Creation Hypothesis (Downers Grove: lnterVarsity Press, 1994), pp. 18-23.

7 See, for example, J. P. Moreland, op. cit., p. l9.

8 Quentin Smith, 1987. “Infinity and the Past”, Philosophy of Science 54:63-75.

9 Craig, op. cit., p. 69.

10 William L. Craig, 1980. “Philosophical and Scientific Pointers to Creation Ex Nihilo”, Journal of the American Scientific Affiliation, 32:6.

11 Craig, op. cit. p. l2.

12 Craig (1979), p. 151.

13 William L. Craig, 1984. Apologetics: An Introduction (Chicago: Moody Press), p. 93.


Translated from WS2000 on 14 February 2005 by ws2html.